Weekly update 6

Sir William George Gillies, "Moorfoot" (1961)


I was about two weeks behind at the beginning of the week. Now I'm just a day or two behind. I accomplished this feat by revising my schedule, frankly, though I did get a bit of work done as well. The path I'm trying to take is somewhat winding: I have to get from creation to the Word to the "truth" of creatures without losing anyone along the way. I'm still figuring out how to finesse that turn from the Word to creatures, but once that's done, the rest of the chapter will write itself. And the next chapter, about freedom and the fall, should also be easy.

In addition to working on Anselm, I led a Bible study on Revelation 11:19-15:4. It was a lot of material, and I thought I could cover it best by focusing on three passages that introduce characters who play a major role in that part of the vision. I found some nice images, which I might as well pass along. We first read about the woman, the child, and the dragon in 12:1-6:


Then there were the two beasts, one from the sea (12:18-13:4)


and one from the land (13:16-18).




We of course talked about the mark of the best, examining calculations both serious


and frivolous.

All that unfortunately left us no time to get the final characters, the followers of the Lamb (14:1-5):



*****

And now for the excerpt: a long and difficult bit that may require a complete overhaul, but at least for now it's getting me closer to Anselm's notion of truth.

            When Anselm first introduced the divine utterance of creation, he left it open whether God would utter creation by means of a single word or many words: “whatever he made, he made it through his innermost utterance (whether by saying individual things by means of individual words, or instead by saying all things at once by means of one word).” Now that he has identified that utterance with the Word who is with God, and is God, Anselm can resolve that issue: the Word is God, and God is supremely simple, so the Word is supremely simple. The Word by which God utters creation is one Word.
            How, then, do we account for the variety and differentiation among created things? Augustine, drawing on the same craftsman analogy that Anselm uses, had argued that of course God must have different conceptions (rationes) for different creatures; it would be absurd to think that God makes a human being and a horse by the same conception. There is a divine idea of a horse, a divine idea of a human being, and so on for each kind of creature; these ideas are in the Word. The apparatus of divine ideas served both a metaphysical and an epistemological function. Metaphysically, it offered an account of universals—that is, of what all things of the same kind have in common—that satisfied both the Platonic intuition that universals are real and the Christian requirement that nothing, not even universals, exist independently of God. Epistemologically, it explained how there can be general or universal knowledge: knowledge, not of this horse and that horse, but of what it is to be a horse.
            Anselm’s insistence on the unity of the Word deprives him of these resources. There is no question that Anselm thinks universals are real, and that we have universal and not merely particular knowledge, but he does not construct a systematic account of universals or even give us the materials with which we might construct such an account on his behalf. Where Augustine would say that the Word contains the blueprint for all creatures, Anselm says that the Word is the blueprint for all creatures. Yet creatures—limited, changing, and fragmented as they are—are wildly unlike the infinite, immutable, and simple Word. How, then, do we make sense of the claim that the Word is the blueprint of creation? Anselm sees the difficulty clearly: “If the Word has no likeness to mutable things, how is it that they were patterned after him?”
            Anselm asks us to consider the relation between a human being and a painting of a human being. The reality of humanity is in an actual human being; in the painting there is a likeness or image of that reality. Similarly, the reality of existence is in the Word; in creatures there is a likeness or image of that reality. You could even say, in one sense, that the Word alone exists (just as you can say that nothing is human except a living human being) because the Word alone, as divine, possesses perfect and unlimited existence. In another sense, however, creatures exist as well, because they have been made by the Word and in accordance with the Word. As the painting is an imitation of the living original, creatures are an imitation of the Word. The greater their resemblance to the Word, the greater their being: living creatures are greater than non-living, creatures capable of perception are greater still, and rational creatures are the greatest of all, because they imitate the Word as closely as any creature can. But the Word in no way depends on creatures to exist, or even to be a Word, any more than a human being depends on his portrait to exist or to be a human being. The Word is the Word of God, not (as it turns out) the Word of creation, because the Word is a perfect likeness of God and not at all a likeness of creation, though creation is a likeness of the Word.
            This is, to be sure, a difficult position to make sense of. Part of the difficulty is that we think of the relation of being like as what we nowadays call a symmetric relation. In a symmetric relation, if x bears that relation to y, y also bears it to x. Being like seems like a strong candidate for being a symmetric relation: if I am like my sister, my sister is like me. So if creatures are like the Word, surely the Word is like creatures. But for Anselm the relevant relation is not being like, but being a likeness of, which is quite plausibly taken as an asymmetric relation. We might say that if my portrait is like me, I am like my portrait; but we would certainly not say that if my portrait is a likeness of me, I am a likeness of my portrait. It is in precisely this sense that creatures are a likeness of the Word but the Word is not a likeness of creatures.
            This explanation gets us some way toward understanding Anselm’s view of the relationship between creation and the Word, but the notion of likeness (or resemblance or imitation—he uses all these expressions) leaves some mysteries unresolved. One such mystery is how different creatures imitate the Word in different ways. Anselm offers us a way of understanding how a human being imitates the Word both in a different way and in a more excellent way than a cat does: the human being has reason, whereas the cat has only the power of sensation. But how does a dog imitate the Word in a different way from a cat? It’s hard to see an answer, and yet presumably creatures can be different from one another only insofar as they imitate the Word in different ways.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

The Georgetown Chronicles continue

Of vanity

Lament for a friendship unhappily lost